Wordtrade LogoWordtrade.com

 

Review Essays of Academic, Professional & Technical Books in the Humanities & Sciences

 

 

Melancholy, Love, and Time: Boundaries of the Self in Ancient Literature by Peter M. Toohey ( University of Michigan Press) Ancient literature features many powerful narratives of madness, depression, melan­choly, lovesickness, simple boredom, and the effects of such psychological states upon individual sufferers. Peter Toohey turns his attention to representations of these emotional states in the classical, Hellenistic, and especially the Roman imperial periods in a study that illuminates the cultural and aesthetic significance of this emotionally charged literature.

Toohey also examines some of the ways that the "self" was (or was not) formulated in ancient literature, looking at conditions that could be said to endanger the fragile stability of "self" and how the "self," in ancient experience, was reestablished. Ancient representations of suicide, the perception of time, and the formulation of leisure, Toohey argues, challenge the widespread orthodoxy that melancholic emotions were somehow "discovered" during the European Enlightenment. Blending ancient literature, ancient art, modern psychological theory, and modern literature into his interpretive matrix, Toohey concludes that, paradoxically, difficult emotional registers represent key modes for buttressing an indi­vidual's sense of self in both the ancient and modern world.

Toohey’s main concern is to demonstrate that there took place in the first and sec­ond centuries of our era (and to a lesser extent in the early Hellenistic period) a shift in the presentation of the self and of self-consciousness in certain key works of the literature of antiquity. There is—or was—a marked change in the mode by which such affective states as melancholia, love, lovesickness, and boredom and such affective registers as time and even leisure are presented. Progressively more, Toohey argues, they become a locus through which the self and self-consciousness gain vivid repre­sentation. There is a thickening or a deepening of the manner by which these emotions and, flowing from this, the self are represented. The presentation, not just of self, but also of self-consciousness, is far more detailed and far more evident in these periods than it is in earlier literature. This is a sense of self (or self-consciousness or self-definition, but not self-knowledge in the Socratic sense) as constituted by inwardness. It is built upon an opposition of "inside-outside," a partitioning off of the self from the world about us. And so it is with the various emotions and psychological registers upon which Toohey focuses.) "Thoughts, ideas, or feelings ... [are] `within' us, while the objects in the world which these mental states bear on are `without,' states Charles Taylor in a different context. He continues to observe that "[human] ca­pacities or potentialities [are] `inner,' awaiting the development which will man­ifest them or realize them in a public world." So it is in this period, but at a cost.

We tend to associate such a presentation of self with recent, post-Enlight­enment literary and social experience. Part of the purpose of Melancholy, Love, and Time is to demonstrate the comparability of this novel experience between its ancient and modern literary representations. To this end Toohey has adduced a number of par­allels between the later ancient and modern depiction of emotions such as those already noted—melancholia, boredom, lovesickness, suicidal urges, and the experience of time. The modern parallels for these emotions and for the presen­tation of self through them are drawn from a promiscuous body of material: novels, nonfiction books, newspapers, art, and ethnological reports. Toohey has used a very broad range of evidence both modern and ancient: Greek and Roman prose and verse authors, Greek and Roman painting, modern prose and paint­ing, and modern newspapers, magazines, and television. As Robert Burton, author of the Anatomy of Melancholy,  might have objected, the resultant effect may seem at times to produce a "rhap­sody of rags gathered together from several dunghills." Notwithstanding such colorful objections, the citation of such material seems to be the best way to go about demonstrating sameness. The range of evidence is justified because Toohey is trying to demonstrate the similarities between the ancient and modern depictions of the various registers of the sentiments or sentimental registers surveyed in Melancholy, Love, and Time. In this way Toohey intends to illustrate that these con­ditions were not recent inventions of periods such as the Enlightenment. How better can one illustrate parallel responses to similar stimuli than by appeal to a wide range of modern parallels?

To insist upon this sameness as it relates to the emergence and maintenance of human affectivities and psychological registers, as they are depicted in an­cient and modern cultural and literary experience, is to insist these are not specific cultural or social artifacts. At any rate, Toohey  has demonstrated the com­mon traits that are shared and exhibited by melancholia, boredom, lovesickness, monkish acedia, the perception and experiencing of time and leisure, and even the drive to do away with oneself. He has also looked briefly at a variety of contagious emotional states, such as the use of the evil eye, "boning," and assault by voodoo. In doing so Toohey attempts to show how they fit within a single experiential template. Still other matters, such as literacy, utopianism, and notions of the Golden Age, are mentioned in passing. The conclusions are that the emotional conditioning to be associated with these topics and registers exhibits a sameness as it relates one to another and through time. The responses embodied in these topics and registers are shared and even predictable. They are capable of being mapped through time, almost in a structuralist fashion.

Despite this commonality, a degree of periodization is possible for the chart­ing of the currency of the different forms taken by these conditions. Toohey indicates the existence of this periodization at the very outset of this study. Where such a periodization of the representation of emotions and of the self is possible, this seems to exist only in the simplest of senses. Thus, through time we see a simple alternation—or better perhaps, an evolutive progress—between apparent polar opposites: a movement from or between activity and passivity, body and mind (interiority), complicity and estrangement, assertion and yielding, complicity and isolation, participation and withdrawal, public and private, the mark and the sign, surface and depth, lack of control and con­trol, and so forth.  Toohey  suggests that this evolutive movement is evident in each of the affective registers treated or mentioned within this book. Thus they relate to the mapping of the self. In fact, the relations between these emotional states and their seemingly oscillating movements can almost be mapped. It is, then, partly through the movement from one set of these qualities to the other that Toohey attempts to establish an approximate periodization for the literary representation (the discursive representation) of emotions and of the self within the periods of the ancient world surveyed in Melancholy, Love, and Time.

Toohey argues that there took place in the first and second centuries of our era (and to a lesser extent during the Hellenistic pe­riod) a shift in the presentation of the self in a number of key works of antiq­uity. This claim raises the issue of the recurrent problem, for historians of psy­chology and psychiatry, of whether an emotional state or sentiment is more prominently mentioned and discussed and defined in a particular era and whether this emotional state or sentiment is in fact more prevalent in that era.

To a large extent, Toohey’s evidence is inconclusive. Most of the ancient witnesses that he presents are derived from literary texts. The evidence is essentially linguistic and therefore skewed by a variety of historical constraints: by genre, above all, but also by the period in which the form was used and by its host lan­guage's current linguistic resources, by the decorum of the language form itself, and even by the style of the language itself (Greek or Latin) in its regional and periodical base, not to mention the constraints under which individual au­thors composed. Toohey attempts to find both diachronically and synchroni­cally parallel passages and utterances. The evidence that he presents therefore tells us more, strictly speaking, about language (or discourse) than about real life.

How can this be justified? In chapter 1, Toohey argues that melancholia was un­derstood in most popular ancient literature as an angry illness. This was largely the case until the middle of the first century of our era. At that point popular literature began to take an interest in melancholia of a depressive form. This is what we understand by the term melancholia. Does this suddenly increased interest in depres­sive melancholy point to an increased prevalence of the condition in real life? Conclusions become more possible if we survey other affective conditions. The registering of the response to erotic infatuation, that Toohey surveys in chapter 2, follows a historical trajectory seeming to match that of melancholia. In popular literature down until the middle of the first century of our era, frus­trated erotic infatuation produces an active or violent reaction, that which we could term mania. Subsequently the reaction privileged in popular literature is a depressive one, of the passive and fretful character that we associate with lovesickness. Boredom is the subject of the third chapter; it appears to evince a close relationship to the pattern for which Toohey argues in the first two chapters. As a passive, named, and "spiritualized" condition, it gains real prominence in the middle of the first century of our era.

The change taking place here is probably not so much to be related to melancholia, lovesickness, or boredom proper but, rather to a shift in the presentation of the self and self-consciousness in a number of key works of ancient literature. There was a thickening or deepening of the manner by which the emotions mentioned were described, and with this came a far greater stress on interior­ity and passivity.

The fourth chapter looks at the famous disease of monks' acedia, a form sometimes of melancholia, sometimes of boredom. Its symptoms match those outlined in chapters 1 and 3. Two aspects are of special interest in the case of acedia. First is the viral-like manner by which this illness was transmitted. One could literally catch this illness that closely resembled melancholia or boredom. Second, this illness has sufficient historical testimony to allow us to rec­ognize that we are here dealing not with discourse but with real life. So what does this infection tell us about melancholia, lovesickness, and boredom? First, the striking resemblance between acedia and these conditions demonstrates the possibility and likelihood of a viral fashion of transmission (perhaps not unlike chronic fatigue syndrome) for the conditions surveyed in chapters 1 through 3 and, relatedly, for this new mode of understanding the self. Second, the historical veracity of the existence of acedia, its transcendence of mere discourse, suggests that the same could be said for the new forms of melancholia, lovesickness, and boredom. One can, therefore, answer tentatively the historical question posed earlier. In the case of the sentiments highlighted in chapters 1 through 3, their prominent mention should be equated with their prominent appearance in real life.

The affective registers surveyed in chapters 5 through 7 reinforce the con­clusions just put forward. Self and self-awareness seem to be regis­tered in much the same way in reflections on suicide, time, and passing time (leisure) as in the cases of melancholia, lovesickness, and boredom. New modes of registering and reflecting on suicide, time, and leisure became prominent, Toohey argues, in the first century of our era. These reflect upon the pre­sentation of self and, in its attendant vocabulary, are reliant on a language that underscores individual passivity and interiority. Toohey  has no doubt that we are here dealing with more than just discourse. The variety of the modes by which this new manner of representing the self is evident suggests that real life is at issue here.

Having said all of this, perhaps now Toohey might be allowed one caveat. The periodization and analysis aim to highlight tendencies, not rock-graven truths. Exceptions may always be found to the patterns and mappings and stratigraphies proposed here. These exceptions cannot be said to invalidate discursive realities. Furthermore, that Toohey’s approach to history is open-ended, even experimental.

It is with some hesitation that Toohey uses the ugly, amorphous, and modish term self within the argument of this book. One can think of no other adequate term, however. What makes this so difficult is that the "self" is so much a subject of debate in philosophical and political theory and in psychoanalytical. The debate can be as bewildering as it can be wearying. Definitions can veer wildly between two ends of a spectrum. At the one end is the apparently rea­sonable assumption that the self is a form of individual consciousness that uses "categories such as resemblance, succession, and causation, that provide the hidden thread holding discrete experience together;” at the other is Lacan's belief that "what we take to be the self is actually a symptom of our inability to accept our inauthenticity.” These two poles are mediated by a concept of the "social self," one that is constructed by (1) how we imagine we appear to the other; (2) how we imagine the other judges us; and (3) pride or mortification as a consequence of number 2.

There are complications. The understanding of "self " will vary, depending on whether one is attempting to register and generalize upon one's own sense of self or that of another. Registering that of another is perhaps easier: one looks in another person for a certain habitual style, attitude, "voice," or emotional response—character in short. Registering one's own sense of self is more tricky. Toohey supposes that the simplest way to think of this is to say that such a sense of identity (or self, or style, or voice, or character) is built on memory and the continuity it implies for potentially discrete experience.

What is memory? It, too, depends on one’s beliefs. In the most plain of un­derstandings, it is consciously remembering the past and, from construing this, establishing a personal, mental continuity that holds "discrete experience to­gether." A Freudian would want to add subconscious memory to this sugges­tion; a Marxist, historical and social forces; a Pythagorean, the inherited soul; a Foucaldian, discourse. All of these, if they have any phenomenological valid­ity, may modify conscious recollection and, with this, the construction of self.

Were we, however, to focus further on this simple sense of personal self, that built on conscious memory, experience would suggest that it is not some-thing that can survive the vicissitudes of memory. Illness, alcohol, strokes, se­nility, Alzheimer's disease, trauma, severe depression, drinking at the river Lethe, and many other comparable events both actual and metaphorical can de­stroy memory. Does this take the self with it? Toohey would say yes. His mother, for example, had for his family the traces of her "self " or character after she had fallen victim to multiple infarct dementia. From his mother's point of view, however, she clearly had no sense of self as she swiftly lost her ability to recognize them and to recall her past. It had vanished as her brain came sadly to resemble Swiss cheese.

The "self " that Toohey  wants to look at in this book is a very simple thing." It is a personal self and relates to our perception of ourselves as autonomous beings, as creatures set apart from others and from the physical world."' This sense of separateness is not something that all creatures possess. Small children do not seem to possess this. Freud, Piaget, and even Lacan have described this child­ish condition more or less concretely. Many people can recall the astonishing childhood insight that they were not part and parcel of the world around, that they had a separate existence. The very old can gradually lose this sense of separateness. Many animals, householders such as dogs and cats, can have little sense of this at all. Watch them.

Mental disease can create havoc with this human sense of separateness, by blurring dangerously the boundaries of the self. By this blurring of boundaries by reference to mania and depression, on which two topics Toohey focuses in this study one can recognize the loss of an autonomous self.. In the former state the individual easily loses a sense of himself or herself as an entity separate from the world about. There is a sort of a catastrophic communion between the individual and the world. The boundaries of the self expand outward and can become wholly blurred. We could compare the condition of the opposite pole, depression. Here the individual becomes so drawn in on himself or herself that the outside world begins to cease to exist as a separate entity. Thus ensues a type of autis­tic state. The boundaries are set dangerously high but are no less blurred.

One should not confuse this form of self-awareness with the type of moral or philosophical self-knowledge urged upon us by the precept "Know thyself " or by Greek admonitions concerning the worth of the unexamined life. Nor should Toohey’s use of the term self be confused with that relating to the represen­tation of the self—in the autobiographical mode by which we represent ourselves and our apparent identity to the world (our race, gender, sexuality; our personality or "voice" or character—the normally visible signs of who we are). That "self" resembles our particular personal "signature." Scholars such as Haijo Westra or Brian Stock suggest that the appearance of this kind of self is very late in ancient literature. They associate this with Augustine's Confessions. Literature to that point was dominated by topic, by a presentation of self that was con­ditioned more by generic constraint and even discourse than by a desire for autobiographical verisimilitude.

The "self " with which Toohey is concerned is far less specific. He is using the term, rather, in the sense of "self-consciousness," as a sense of oneself as a sen­tient being, separate from those about. Such a sense of self is built on a real­ization that what matters is within us. It is built finally on a sense of alienation from others and from the world. Such a sense of self is not shared by all crea­tures. As Toohey has noted, observe the dog or cat (on most occasions), or the very young, or many of the very old.

When such a registering of self is apparent in literary texts, it is built upon an opposition of "inside-outside," a partitioning off of the self from the world about. We could speculate that the sense of self evident in such texts may evince a standing outside oneself, a concern almost to watch, to weigh up, and to react to one 's emotional and physical state almost as if it were another. Such a representation of self may involve the highlighting of an individual's inner mental processes. It may involve not just a partitioning between the inner self and the outer world but also a partitioning between the body (approximating the outer world) and the self (approximating the inner world). It is as if the subject stands at a remove from his or her emotional reactions. The subject watches his or her reactions and may feel powerless in their face. There emerges a disjunction between the body and a person's consciousness of it. It is for this reason that Toohey has made so much of Hostius Quadra in the final chapter in this book.

The sense of self Toohey discusses is built on boundaries. These boundaries between the self and others and the world are not achieved with ease. Throughout one's life, they require constant renegotiation and recalibration. In the first part of this book, Toohey demonstrates how in an­cient literary experience, these boundaries could be blurred or even destroyed or could seem not to exist at all. He illustrates the suffering that can result from the blurring of these boundaries. (So in the first four chapters of this book, he illustrates how a variety of psychological conditions—melancholia, boredom, lovesickness, and acedia—can lead to the breakdown of the self and can lead an individual even to death.) In the second half of this book, Toohey demonstrates how these boundaries, when threatened, can be remapped, renegotiated, and reformulated. (So, by examining some ancient experiences of suicide, time, and leisure, he  shows how the self can be shored up against disinte­gration, how it can, in the face of psychological trauma, be reformulated.) Toohey suggests that this process of renegotiation takes place through a self-assertion based especially upon an acceptance of alienation and estrangement. The psychological reintegration of the self is achieved through an acceptance of es­trangement, or to put it another way, an acceptance of the slippery relationship between a person's "inner" and "outer" (almost words and things). This is not a very postmodern conclusion to reach. As good a critic of clas­sical literature as David Wiles maintains, following Lacan and others, that the self is fragmented and, in this sense, unstable. Agreeing with the latter definition, though not perhaps in the way meant by such Lacanians Toohey studies the protagonists in this book to establish, almost by subterfuge, rock-solid psyches, mostly by complaining about their psychic fragility. Wiles also suggests that the self is "compounded of a series of discursive networks."' That this cannot be the case is illustrated again and again by the experiential sameness of reactions produced by Australian Aboriginals and in the lovesickness of Sappho, Chari­cleia, and Chaereas. It is illustrated above all by acedia, as Toohey surveys it in chapter 4. What can one say? The ego is autonomous and highly developed. The self is the product of pain and alienation and a product of total otherness from fam­ily, from community, and, paradoxically, even from the self itself. It is defined by the chasm, enforced on a child at a very young age, between the individual and the world about. The sense of self, at least the sense of self exhibited by the characters analyzed in this book, is permanent and durable and is formulated from a basic set of constraints. It makes itself felt in a standard set of modali­ties. There is, Toohey shows, neither anything terribly new nor anything terribly fragmented about the self.

One of the more unexpected conclusions of this mode of argument is that measure of depression is as inevitable as it is good for you. That may sound offensive as a conclusion to the many sufferers of this condition. Yet the advantages provided by the self-awareness bestowed by a modicum of depression will become apparent. At least in the realms surveyed within this book, espe­cially in chapters 5 through 7, it seems to provide a measure of protection against the sickness brought on by the blurring of the boundaries of the self. Toohey argues in chapter 8 that self-awareness is built on a sense of distance from oneself, on a capacity to observe oneself. This is a type of alienation that is tan­tamount to mild depression (can it be any other way?). Toohey suggests in that chapter, furthermore, that should the distance become too great, the risk run repre­sents a type of psychological disintegration to be associated with depression. Should the gulf become too narrow, even negligible, the risk run is that of mania and autism. Self-awareness, a concomitant of mild melancholy, seems, then, to guard against the dangers of suffering major reactive depression or mania (or to put it in other words, destructive inaction versus unthinking and destructive reaction). Self-awareness rests on the erection of boundaries between the self and others, between the self and the physical world. The alienation resulting from this is viscerally painful, but it does highlight the need for psychological and attitudinal vigilance. Instinct, thus, is controlled only by these boundaries. This study offers not only some insight into historical psychology but also some of the more subtle uses of classical stories in our own time to celebrate the self as a meaning bearing figment of live lived.

Subjecting Verses: Latin Love Elegy and the Emergence of the Real by Paul Allen Miller (Princeton University Press) It's always time for someone to discuss the context from which the genre of love elegy emerged. Paul Allen Miller shares his fascination with this poetry that emerged suddenly, sparked, and then disappeared all within a period of fifty years or so. His interpretations and methods of reading elegy are generally smart, though I remain disappointed that some of the uncertainty concerning love elegy finds a kind of analytical resolution in the clarity of psychoanalytic discourse. The chapter on reading the poems of Tibullus is utterly fascinating. The introductory chapter cleanly exhibits the psychoanalytic terminology used throughout in such a way that most of the explanations that use it will be clear to those who don't read Ecrits for kicks. Other chapters provide encounters with Catullus, Propertius, the idea of Gallus, and Ovid.  However, "Maitre, there seems to be a Symbolic in the Imaginary of my Real," is a sentence that would not be entirely out of place in this book. The wedding of much theory (Jameson, Foucault, Lacan) is consonant with the bounty of citations philosopher Slavoj Zizek receives, seemingly more than any philologist who actually works on Roman elegy. It also seemed that fewer passages of poetry, but more selected words, received discussion than a more comprehensive study might merit, but the author does well to traverse the lifespan of the art and relate its habits to the concerns of the day. There are a couple of textual errors and one of the sources is cited in text without a bibliographical referent.

The complexity of elegy Paul Allen Miller puts on glorious display. The argument that the ideologically split selves of poets in an uncertain age begat poems offering politically prismatic effects seems remotely analogous to Glenn Most's essay elsewhere on the rage for poetic dismemberment during the reign of Nero, in the sense that both authors consider the poets concerned to be keenly aware of the political and cultural trends of the age. The book was invigorating and frustrating for this reader, but on such an exciting topic the many hits may outnumber the misses.

Headline 3

insert content here