J
Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on the Kyoto School by
James Heisig (University of Hawaii Press) Reviewed for H-Buddhism by
Gereon Kopf, Luther College, Department of Religion and Philosophy.
James Heisig's Philosophers of Nothingness, the English version
of his Filosofos de la nada, appeared in 2001 and has ever since
provoked a series of superlative reviews, published in the common
venues dealing with Japanese thought and comparative philosophy,
praising it, for the most part, as a brilliant milestone in the
scholarship on the Kyoto school. And such it is in many ways. In
this book, Heisig presents a clear, insightful, and accessible
I exposition of the philosophy advanced by the three arguably most
important thinkers of the so-called Kyoto-school--Kitarou Nishida,
Hajime Tanabe, and Keiji Nishitani--that was sorely lacking in the
English and German speaking world as well as, I assume, in most
languages other than Japanese.
In three sections, which are enclosed by an orientation and a prospectus, Heisig portrays the philosophies of Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani, focusing on their conceptual achievements, the ventures into political thought all three thinkers engaged during the militarism of Shouwa Japan, and the religious dimension central to these philosophies.
He does this in an extremely engaging style that draws the reader
into the world of Kyoto school thought and kindles a passion for the
issues Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani had been struggling with
throughout their careers. In addition, Heisig's strategy to separate
technical arguments from the main body of the text is, in my
opinion, brilliant. This method makes not only the text immensely
readable, but the narrative notes Heisig presents in an addendum of
roughly seventy pages also constitute the perfect venue for
following up different arguments that, while sometimes only
tangential to the main thread of the book, nevertheless provide
insightful, if not necessary, information. Since Heisig thus gathers
the notes by section rather than assigning them to individual terms
or citations, Brett Davis suggests that this method may make "the
task of tracking down a particular reference a bit cumbersome."[1]
Yet, citing the references in the order in which the quotations
appear would make them easily accessible and still maintain an
otherwise superb format.
One of the main contributions of Heisig's book is his argument
that the thought of the Kyoto school thinkers constitutes
essentially a world philosophy or, at least, a call for one. In
short, Heisig contends that Kyoto school philosophy transcends the
borders of a parochial philosophy and provides the impetus and the
method to do philosophy that draws from various philosophical
traditions. Heisig argues that "even this very idea of comparative
philosophy ends up confirming the assumption that the only _world_
philosophy is philosophy done in the western mold. This is the mold
that Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani have broken, though the
consequences of that rupture have only just begun to affect those
engaged in the classical western philosophy around the world" (p.
8). Heisig here not only describes the project of the Kyoto school
but further boldly and justifiably challenges the hypothesis that
philosophy must be "philosophy in the western mold." In addition, he
points out, whether consciously or not, the irony with which
Heidegger's claim identifying philosophy with the tradition emerging
from the Greeks declares a geographically restricted philosophy to
be universal.
The Kyoto school philosophers suggest an alternative methodologically by interweaving "Western" and Buddhist ideas in the case of Nishida, and arguments in the case of Nishitani, and conceptually in the form of Nishida's "global world" (ekaitekisekai) or "world of world history" (rekishitekisekai) and their variations on the notion of "absolute nothingness" (zettaimu).[2] I will return to the latter concept below.
The key to the conundrum of "world philosophy" lies, as Heisig is well aware, in the very terminology "philosophy" itself. Of course, the academic discipline of philosophy takes its name from the Greek word philosophia, first used by Homer and Herodotus, but the etymology of a name does not preclude other traditions. P. T. Raju argued in 1962, in his Introduction to Comparative Philosophy, that the Sanskrit darshana and the Chinese jia_similarly denote a philosophical discourse in the narrow sense. Gene Blocker's World Philosophy: An East-West Comparative Introduction to Philosophy more forcefully attempts to create one world philosophy by combining the foundational thinkers of Greece, India, and China to introduce and discuss the fundamental issues of and arguments in metaphysics, epistemology, etc.
It does seem, therefore, more than appropriate that the push towards a world philosophy initiated by the philosophers of the Kyoto school and their contemporaries in India, such as Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, is supplemented by fundamental discussions on the nature of philosophy.
Heisig's three-level definition of philosophy as a "more or less
conscious myth or framework of values," a "more critical body of
thought dealing with ultimate questions, systematically recorded and
transmitted," and the "particular tradition that began in Athens"
offers a good starting point (p. 7), but the fact that he is now
preparing a symposium on "Re-defining Philosophy" illustrates the
importance rethinking of philosophy has for the project of a world
philosophy.[3]
Let me state very clearly that I completely agree with Heisig's
argument and sympathize with his concerns; however, the project of a
"world philosophy" raises a few important questions, especially with
regards to the categories we use. I would like to focus here on
those pertaining to Heisig's project in _Philosophers of
Nothingness_. A malicious intent could misconstrue his argument that
Kyoto school philosophers, as the most prominent representation of
Japanese philosophy, laid the foundations for a world philosophy to
equate the three terms Kyoto school philosophy, Japanese philosophy,
and world philosophy. This is of course not the case, but headings
such as "Japanese Philosophy as World Philosophy" beg the question
of what our categories mean. Is membership in the Kyoto school
defined by direct lineage or even as closed society limited to
"Nishida, Tanabe, and their disciples," as Masakatsu Fujita
suggests, or is it possible to define Kyoto school philosophy by
method or content as the title Philosophers of Nothingness
implies?[4]
Similarly, is Japanese philosophy defined by geography, ethnicity
of the author, language in which it is conducted, or by some
intangible essence evoked by, among others D. T. Suzuki and, more
recently, Takeshi Umehara? What are the parameters of a world
philosophy that transcends provinciality and invites a variety of
traditions and methodologies without becoming a meaningless label?
These questions are, of course, immensely difficult and Heisig does
an exemplary job of negotiating the difficulties of and traps
inherent in these definitions. For example, he presents the
etymology of the term "Kyoto school" invented by Jun Tosaka in 1932
and varying lists of members suggested by the 1998 Dictionary of
Philosophy and Ideas (Tetsugaku shisou jiten) and a number of
scholars ranging from Yoshinori Takeuchi to Futoshi Shibayama, in
his notes. He also is actively pursuing the question of what
constitutes Japanese Philosophy in a source book he is presently
preparing together with Thomas Kasulis and John Maraldo.[5] Finally,
his decision to limit his discussion to the triad of Nishida,
Tanabe, and Nishitani is warranted since his focus is the variations
on the philosophy of nothingness of which Nishida, Tanabe, and
Nishitani represent three fundamental approaches; and it was
probably the works of Tanabe and Nishitani that brought the
philosophies of Nishida and the Kyoto school to the prominence they
have today. This of course does not preclude the observation that an
English language exposition of Kyoto school philosophy that includes
the so-called minor thinkers of the Kyoto school in addition to the
already available Sourcebook of Modern Japanese Philosophy by David
A. Dilworth, Valdo H. Vieglielmo, and Agustin Jacinto Zavala would
make an important contribution to comparative philosophy.
My sole disappointment with this book is that Heisig did not make
more of the title Philosophers of Nothingness. Not only could this
phrase be used to avoid the question of whether or not to define the
Kyoto school by lineage and to simultaneously highlight the main
contribution of these philosophers, it also leads straight to the
center of philosophies of Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani. In fact, I
believe that the notion of nothingness, even though it is not the
one I would choose,`could be used as a heuristic device to unlock
the intricacies of their philosophies. Nishida, as Heisig states
rather succinctly, was driven to find the one absolute principle
that grounds all of thought. In fact, his work can be read as an
exploration of possible candidates to function as such a principle.
In some sense he found it in the notion of "absolute nothingness"
"that is 'absolved' of any opposition that could render it relative,
so that its only opposition to the world of being is that of an
absolute to a relative" (p. 62) and, at the same time, that "it
allowed individuals, just as they are, to stand in opposition to one
another as absolute contradictories" (p. 64).
This principle constitutes Nishida's response to the philosophical problems evoked by the dualism of European enlightenment thought, especially Kantianism, and, at the same time, the founding block of his philosophy on which he built, or tried to erect, his philosophies of history and religion. The place where Nishida succeeded most in developing this notion of "absolute nothingness," that combined the oppositions of self and other, subject and predicate without dissolving them, was his philosophy of religion, to be exact, his notion of "inverse correspondence." This concept summarizes Nishida's belief that "the stronger the opposition, the more deeply rooted the identity" (p.103). Tanabe reinterpreted the notion of "absolute nothingness," he had inherited from his teacher Nishida, and located it squarely within the immanent realm of oppositions. While sounding frequently similar to Nishida's later philosophy, which undoubtedly received some influence from Tanabe's thought, Heisig clearly identifies their main difference:
"For Tanabe absolute nothingness ... is not an unmediated
universal ...itself lacking in differentiation.... It does not
belong to being, but at the same time its activity is only manifest
in the world of being, refracted, for example, in the ethical
activities of self-negating praxis" (p. 120). While Nishida's
"absolute nothingness" shares this ambivalence of transcendent yet
immanent, it does privilege the moment of identity, if only by
virtue of Nishida's terminology.
Tanabe's version of absolute nothingness instead is historical,
in that in the form of the "specific" (shu) it mediates, but does
not identify the universal and the individual. Similarly, it is this
perseverance of the moments of differentiation and otherness in the
form of "other-power" (tariki) that enables his "absolute critique"
of "the hubris of reason" (p. 161) and a methodology Heisig
describes as "philosophy-in-religion" (p. 162). Finally, Nishitani
replaces the notion of absolute nothingness with that of emptiness
to stress its indebtedness to the Buddhist tradition and to shift
from the search for a foundational logic to the rhetoric of the
standpoint. This "standpoint of emptiness, then, is not so much a
philosophical 'position' as it is the achievement of an original
self-awareness ... compared to which all other consciousness is
caught in the fictional darkness of ignorance" (p. 222). Nishitani
bases on this standpoint and the notion of selflessness it entails
not only his philosophy of religion or what can be called one
attempt at a Zen philosophy, but more concretely an ethics and
philosophy of science that conquers the alienation engendered by
egocentrism in its philosophical sense and nihilism. In this way,
the notion of nothingness does facilitate a comparison that brings
out the differences between the three main Kyoto school philosophers
and, simultaneously, focuses their contribution to a world
philosophy.
The questions, however, that remain in my mind are as follows:
how will these variations on the philosophy of nothingness "be seen
to have made a more lasting impact on twentieth century philosophy"
than neo-Kantianism (p. 260)? How can these philosophies be
extracted from "their naïve contexts" (p. 264) and be evaluated, not
merely as an interesting historical phenomenon, but rather a major
contribution towards a world philosophy? Or as Joseph O'Leary puts
it, "how can we sift what is living from what is dead in the
philosophy of the Kyoto school?"[6] My suspicion is that the answer
to these questions lies exactly in developing something akin to a
philosophy of nothingness from the sources of the Kyoto school
thinkers that does not take as its orientation Kantian or
neo-Kantian philosophy, but, as Heisig implicitly suggests in his
prospectus, contemporary thought. If this can be done successfully,
I believe, the philosophies of the Kyoto school and especially the
principle or standpoint of absolute nothingness will be able to
provide a promising paradigm for a philosophy beyond parochial
mindsets and boundaries.
In the final section, I would like to give a brief nod to a few
topics ever present in the scholarship on the Kyoto school. First,
concerning a possible interpretation of Kyoto school philosophy as
Buddhist thought Heisig clearly and succinctly states that "the
Kyoto school philosophers are eastern and they are Buddhist. But
their aim and context is neither eastern nor Buddhist" (p. 8);
rather their orientation is the Continental philosophy of their
time, while their interpretations of Buddhism is idiosyncratic at
best and more often than not have been rejected by Buddhologists.
Second, Heisig's judgment is equally to the point when he tackles
the perennial debate on whether Nishida supported the Japanese
nationalism of his time. In short, while Nishida "lent validity to
the question of the identity of the Japanese spirit" and while "his
idea of nation shared with the ideological propaganda important
assumptions about … the special mission of the Japanese people," the
universalism of his general philosophical system and "inspiration"
was in marked contrast to his adventures into political thought.
Third, even though the notion of no-self constitutes a centerpiece
of Kyoto school philosophy, Heisig correctly acknowledges that
Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani failed, for the most part, to
acknowledge the polyvalence as well as the ethical implications of
this concept. All three instances reveal not only Heisig's
discerning insights but also his fair evaluation of Kyoto school
philosophy avoiding an uncritical adherence to as well as an equally
uncritical rejection of the philosophers of nothingness.
Finally, I would like to comment on Heisig's idiosyncratic
translation of "_shu no ronri_" as "the logic of the specific." I
find his choice of word intriguing and preferable to the
traditional, literal, rendition of the Japanese original as "logic
of species," not the least because it serves to distinguish Tanabe's
interpretation from Hegel's terminology (p. 314). However, this may
be a case where the reader could benefit from an explanation of this
choice of words or even a Kanji glossary, especially since Heisig's
translation constitutes a break with not only the general use of
Tanabe scholarship but also with his own rendition of "_shu_" as
"species" in two essays prior to 1994.[7]
In the end, Heisig's book stands out as one of the most
insightful and fascinating studies of the philosophies of the Kyoto
school that simultaneously contributes to scholarship on and
functions as an introduction to the philosophies of nothingness.
Notes
[1]. Brett Davis, "Introducing the Kyoto School as World
Philosophy: Reflections on James Heisig's _Philosophers of
Nothingness_," _Eastern Buddhist_ 34, no. 2 (2002), p. 146.
[2]. Ironically, Nishida developed these two concepts in the
context of his politically controversial _The Problem of Japanese
Culture_ (_Nihon bunka no mondai_) to argue that Japan, as any other
culture has to become "worldly," today we would say "global," in
order to theorize the role Japan has in the world. It shows the
tension between Nishida's "political philosophy" and his
"fundamental inspirations" and supports Heisig's interpretation that
the former distracted from the latter (p.99). Kitarou Nishida _The
Collected Works of Kitarou Nishida_ (_Nishida kitarou zenshuu_),
vol. 12 (Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1988), pp. 275-394.
[3]. For further information see
http://www.nazan-u.ac.ip/SHUBUNKEN/projects/projects.htm.
[4]. Masakatsu Fujita, _The Philosophy of the Kyoto School_
(_Kyoto gakuha no tetsugaku_) (Kyoto: Shouwadou, 2001), p. ii.
[5]. For further information see
http://www.nazan-u.ac.ip/SHUBUNKEN/projects/projects.htm
[6]. Joseph O'Leary, "Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on
the Kyoto School," _Japanese Journal of Religious Studies_ 29,
no.1-2 (2002), pp. 97-102.
[7]. James W. Heisig, foreword, _Philosophy of Metanoetics_, Trans. Takeuchi Yoshinori, Valdo Vigliemo, and James Heisig (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1986), pp. vii-xxx; and James W.
Heisig, "The 'Self That is Not a Self': Tanabe's Dialectics of
Self-Awareness," in _The Religious Philosophy of Tanabe Hajime_, ed.
Taitetsu Unno and James W. Heisig (Berkeley: Asian Humanities Press,
1990), pp. 277-290.
Reviewed for H-Buddhism by Gereon Kopf, Luther College, Department of Religion and Philosophy. H-NET BOOK REVIEW Published by H-Buddhism@h-net.msu.edu Reviewed for H-Buddhism by Richard Nance, University of Chicago. Copyright (c) 2004 by H-Net, all rights reserved. H-Net permits the redistribution and reprinting of this work for nonprofit, educational purposes, with full and accurate attribution to the author, web location, date of publication, originating list, and H-Net: Humanities & Social Sciences Online.
THE MONK AND THE PHILOSOPHER: A Father and Son Discuss the Meaning of Life by Jean Francois Revel, Matthieu Ricard ($24.00, hardcover, 336 pages, Schocken Books; ISBN: 0805241620) Paperback
Jean-Francois Revel, a pillar of French intellectual life in our time, became world-famous for his challenges to both Communism and Christianity. Twenty-seven years ago, his son, Matthieu Ricard, gave up a promising career as a scientist to study Tibetan Buddhism not as a detached observer but by immersing himself in its practice under the guidance of its greatest living masters.
Meeting in an inn overlooking Kathmandu, these two profoundly thoughtful men explored the questions that have occupied humankind throughout its history, Does life have meaning? What is consciousness? Is man free? What is the value of scientific and material progress? Why is there suffering, war, and hatred? Their conversation is not merely abstract: they ask each other questions about ethics, rights, and responsibilities, about knowledge and belief, and they discuss frankly the differences in the way each has tried to make sense of his life.
Utterly absorbing, inspiring, and accessible, this remarkable dialogue engages East with West, ideas with life, and science with the humanities, providing wisdom on how to enrich the way we live our lives. The undercurrents and subtle tensions makes this one of the most thoughtful and humane exchanges on the East versus West front. Recommended as a possible classic and milestone in the Buddhist conversion of Western science and philosophy.
JEAN-FRANCOIS REVEL, a member of the Academe Franaise, was born in 1924. He studied and taught philosophy but abandoned university teaching to concentrate on writing. He was editor for many years of the influential political weekly LExpress .His books, including the bestseller Without Marx or Jesus and How Democracies Perish, have gained worldwide recognition.
MATTHIEU RICARD lives in the Shechen Monastery in Nepal. Born in France in 1946, he received his doctorate in molecular biology from the Institut Pasteur in Paris. In 1972 he decided to forsake his scientific career to better concentrate on his Buddhist studies, which he had begun years earlier. He has published Journey to Enlightenment, a book of photographs about his teacher, Dilgoentse Rinpoche (one of the most eminent Tibetan masters of our times and a teacher to The Dalai Lama), as well as translations of many Buddhist texts. He often accompanies The Dalai Lama to France as his personal interpreter.
EXCERPT:
J.F. I can understand how useful it is for the person whos acting to have the
wisdom that enables him to stand back from his subjective particularities, his own
passions, and thus from his own self, and to consider something wider than the Self, whose
reality he relativizes as much as possible. It guarantees that whatever he does will have
a much greater mastery, will be more universal, will have more meaning for others, and
that hell be better able to understand the world and act on himself. I think,
nonetheless, that all attempts to annihilate the self so as to anaesthetize forever the
feeling of confronting adverse, irksome circumstances, the feeling that there are moral
choices to be made, mistakes to avoid, that human action isnt always clear-sighted,
lucid, and effective in short, all the efforts human thought has gone to in order to calm
us and get rid of that uncertain but responsible side of things have always failed.
M. The West seems to find it very difficult to understand how recognizing that the self has no true existence doesnt stand in the way of determination, strength of mind and action in the slightest. Instead, it opens our eyes wide to the causes of happiness and suffering. Its a recognition that makes action very precise. Belief in a self isnt what gives force to judgment, its what blocks it. If our actions arent always clear-sighted, courageous, lucid, and effective, as you say, its because were the plaything of our attachment to the self. Its said, The viewpoint of the sage is higher than the sky, and his discernment in terms of the laws of cause and effect is finer than flour. You cant rebel against what youve sown yourself, but you can build the future by knowing how to distinguish between what leads to misery and what liberates you from it. Thats very different from fatalistically espousing an inevitable future.
].F There, I agree with you completely, in the sense that what the Stoics, and Spinoza too, wanted to do to make us more peaceful was to demonstrate that nothing could have happened other than what actually happens.
M. Weve spoken a lot of Buddhism as a way of giving meaning to life. But what is it that gives meaning to life for you, and for the trend of thinking that you represent?
J.F First of all, I dont represent any trend of thinking. I do my best to understand the systems that exist or have existed in the past, and thats already hard enough. But in trying to answer you, Id like to fill in the background, as it were, of the diverse directions that Western thought has taken. Since the birth of Greek civilization which is taken as the starting point of Western culture there have been three main types of answer to the question of the meaning of life. The first is the religious answer, especially since the great monotheistic religions, Judaism, Christianity, and Islam have been predominant. This answer places the finality of existence in the beyond, or in a truth whose nature is transcendent, and therefore in all the steps to be taken and laws to be respected to ensure the personal salvation of the immortal soul. Each person will experience eternal life in the beyond depending on his or her merits in this life here below. Broadly speaking, this is the basis on which the West with the help of religions which all, as it happens, came from the Middle East has built its search for the meaning of life for the last several thousand years. It hasnt prevented each individual from seeking happiness in this world here below through the whole variety of actions that belonging to earthly reality, from the farmer trying to achieve a good harvest up to the king trying to bump off anyone who offends or challenges him, or the businessman trying to make money. You could say that apart from religious people in a strict sense monks, or mystics, whose everyday life coincided with the ideal of salvation all the rest sought happiness in a more or less empirical way, not excluding what religion calls sin, but nevertheless still seeking eternal happiness in the hereafter. The two goals were compatible, since the search for eternal happiness implied the notion of pardon, confession, absolution, and redemption for all the sins committed down below.