Contemporary Buddhist Ethics by Damien Keown (Curzon
Routledge) This collection of essays on Buddhist views of ethical and current
ethical problems offers a rich introduction to Buddhist thought and tradition as
well as contemporary practical ethical reasoning. Not to be ignored by
ethicists.
In terms of the structure of the book, the first two
chapters introduce the reader to important issues regarding the theoretical
nature of Buddhist ethics and the sources of Buddhist moral precepts. An obvious
question to ask at the outset is: How are we to classify Buddhist ethics in
terms of the categories evolved in the study of the ethics in the West? As James
Whitehill observes in the first chapter, contemporary Buddhism increasingly
seeks to make itself understood in modern terms and to respond to contemporary
conditions. In his view, Buddhism's legitimization in the West can be partially
met by demonstrating that Buddhist morality is a virtue-oriented,
characterbased, community-focused ethics, and has much in common with the
Western `ethics of virtue' tradition.
Whitehill takes the view that the earlier generation of the
study of Buddhist ethics focused on escape from Victorian moralism, and was
incomplete. He now sees a new generation of Western Buddhists emerging, for whom
the `construction' of a Buddhist way of life involves community, commitment and
moral `practices.' By keeping its roots in a character formed as `awakened
virtue' and a community guided by an integrative soteriology of wisdom and
morality, he believes that Western Buddhism can avoid the twin temptations of
rootless liberation in an empty `emptiness,' on the one hand, and universalistic
power politics, on the other.
In describing Buddhist ethics as an `ethics of virtue,'
Whitehill is pointing to consistent and essential features of the Buddhist way
of life. But, perhaps more importantly, he is describing Buddhist ethics by
means of an interpretative framework very much alive in Western and Christian
ethics, namely that interpretation of ethics most recently associated with
thinkers like Alasdair Maclntyre and Stanley Hauerwas. Whitehill suggests that
the virtue ethics tradition is the most congenial Western counterpart to
Buddhism. Virtue ethics, he believes, provides a means of understanding Buddhist
ethics, and reciprocally Buddhist ethics offers the West a way of expanding its
scope, which in the past may have been been too elitist, rationalistic, and
anthropocentric. On this basis Whitehill predicts some likely future directions
and limits for Buddhism in a postmodern world.
In the following chapter Charles Prebish explores the
foundations of traditional Buddhist ethics as found in the twin strands of the
Vinaya, or Monastic Code, and in sila, commonly translated as `morality,' or
`moral virtue.' Prebish draws the following distinction between them: `Unlike
the Vinaya, which is externally enforced, sila refers to the internally enforced
ethical framework by which the monk or nun structures his or her life.' So
on which of -these foundations should contemporary Buddhist
ethics be based? Many scholars incline towards the Vinaya as the primary source
for ethical norms, but Prebish finds
Advancing beyond this, Prebish poses a further question.
Granted that Ma is the proper foundation for Buddhist ethics, how does Ma itself
relate to the other important soteriological components of the Buddhist path to
nirvana? The Eightfold Path, which is the royal road to nirvana, is
traditionally divided into three component parts: Morality (Ma), Meditation
(samadhi), and Wisdom (prajna). Some scholars have seen morality as simply a
preliminary step on the way to nirvana, one that is subsequently transcended or
left behind. This view is nowadays less influential, and Prebish emphasizes that
all three components of the path are interrelated and, when developed,
collectively constitute nirvana.
Having established the priority of Ma for any analysis of
Buddhist ethics, Prebish goes on to examine the understanding of the term in
early Sutra and Abhidharma literature, and then in Mahayana texts. The latter
pose a number of interesting challenges, for certain sources seem to authorise
the transgression of the traditional moral precepts in special circumstances. In
doing this they invoke the doctrine of `skilful means' (upaya-kausalya) by way
of justification. This holds that when motivated by compassion and informed by
wisdom, a bodhisattva (or saint) may - in exceptional circumstances - violate
even the most basic precepts, such as the one against taking life. These sources
seem to be moving in the direction of a situation ethics,' albeit with certain
strict provisos.
Having researched the early material, Prebish next turns
his attention to its relevance for the modern world. As noted above, many of the
concerns we face today are not discussed in the ancient texts. How do we bridge
the gap between the moral foundations of the tradition and contemporary ethical
dilemmas? Drawing on ideas from postmodernism and elsewhere, Prebish discusses
various strategies that can be adopted to make the texts speak to our present
needs. Referring to recent work by Harold Coward, he proposes the notion of
dialogue with an `open canon' after the style of the Mahayana, which continued
to produce new literature to speak to new situations. What is required is a way
of approaching the literature that is `is
truly transtemporal and transcultural.' Moreover, since the
vast majority of Western Buddhists are laity rather than monks, any new
methodology must tailor its message to the concerns of lay life, and take into
account developments such as democratization, feminism, and alternative
lifestyles.
Prebish concludes by identifying two key traditional
ethical frameworks that should have a place in fashioning a bridge between the
old and new. The first is the four brahmaviharas or `Divine Abodes,' consisting
of love (maitri), compassion (karuna), sympathetic joy (mudita), and equanimity
(upeksa). The second is that of the six paramitas or 'perfections,' of giving
(dana), morality (sila), patience (ksanti), vigour (virya), meditation
(samadhi), and wisdom (prajna). The first of these is drawn from the Theravada
tradition and the second from the Mahayana. His hope is that together `they
might be reinterpreted conjointly through an entirely new commentarial
literature' in order to reconfigure Buddhist ethics for the modern world.
Turning to the first of the six applied ethical issues to
be considered in the book, it is difficult to think of a more urgent or topical
question for Buddhism in the late twentieth century than human rights. Human
rights issues in which Buddhism has a direct involvement, notably in the case of
With respect to human rights, an important preliminary
question would seem to be whether traditional Buddhism has any understanding of
what is meant by `human rights' at all. Indeed, it may be thought that since the
concept of `rights' is the product of an alien cultural tradition it would be
utterly inappropriate to speak of rights of any kind - `human' or otherwise - in
a Buddhist context. Even if it was felt that these objections were overstated,
and that the issue of human rights does have a legitimate place on the Buddhist
agenda, there would still remain the separate and no less difficult question of
how human rights were to be grounded in Buddhist doctrine, particularly in the
light of the fact that the tradition itself provides little precedent or
guidance in this area. This chapter offers a preliminary exploration of the
questions raised above. It concludes that it is legitimate to speak of both
`rights' and `human rights' in Buddhism, and proposes a ground for human rights
in Buddhist doctrine.
But are human beings the only creatures that have rights?
One feature of Buddhism that has attracted much attention in the West is its
different evaluation of the importance and status of animals. Although often
expressed in a humorous context, the fact that according to Buddhism a person
`can come back as an ant' or as a member of another animal species, is one of
the better known - if least well understood - Buddhist beliefs among Westerners.
This notion, known to Buddhists as the doctrine of `rebirth,' has profound
implications for the way Buddhists view and respond ethically to the animal
kingdom. In his chapter on `Buddhism and Animal Rights' Paul Waldau sets out to
discuss three questions: (1) What does `animal rights' involve? (2) What are the
Buddhist tradition's views of other animals? and (3) How might we relate
Buddhist insights to the admittedly modern notions and terminology used when the
many versions of `animal rights' are discussed?
After clarifying what the notion of `animal rights' means,
Waldau explores the attitude of the Buddhist tradition towards non-human
animals. References to animals are abundant in Buddhist literature, but the
texts display complex and at times inconsistent views about the animal kingdom.
Waldau identifies two `faces' of Buddhism in this respect. In terms of the
first, Buddhism does not restrict moral protection to the human species alone.
Thus the First Precept, unlike the Sixth Commandment (as almost universally
interpreted in the Christian tradition), prohibits intentionally killing or
causing harm to animals as well as to humans. From this perspective, there would
appear to be a moral parity between human and other species. The second `face'
of Buddhism, however, is less benign, and in many respects this general view of
animals in Buddhism may be characterised as negative. This is because to exist
as an animal is - in terms of the hierarchical Buddhism doctrine of rebirth - to
be reborn in a state of woe. It is a kind of purgatory produced by bad karma,
and is a punishment for evil conduct in former lives. Existence as an animal has
few positive aspects: life is perilous and likely to be cut short at any time by
human or other predators. Furthermore, there is little chance of improving one's
lot in terms of spiritual development, since animals lack the intellectual
capabilities to enable them to advance in the Dharma. The best that can be hoped
for is that in the course of time whatever evil karma caused one to be reborn as
an animal will exhaust itself and one will return again to the human world.
Buddhism appears to take little interest in the different capacities and
abilities of the diverse animal species, preferring instead to lump them
together and contrast them as a group with human beings, invariably in a
negative way. Furthermore, Buddhism does not appear to object to the
instrumental use of animals, as in the case of elephants that are kept in
captivity and used for manual labour after being subjected to often painful
techniques of training.
Although the Buddhist view of non-human animals is thus a
mixed one,
Environmental ethics is the subject of the following
chapter by Ian Harris. Harris makes an important point at the outset, a point
also made elsewhere in this collection. This takes the form of a caution against
succumbing to the dangers of anachronism when confronting ancient texts and
traditions with the concerns of modernity. Contemporary concerns such as animal
rights and ecology simply did not feature as distinct topics in the
philosophical agenda of the ancients. For this reason, there is little sustained
discussion of these matters in the texts. Moreover, given that the texts often
seem to present a `blank screen,' there exists the danger of projecting onto
them contemporary ideologies which are based on alien cultural foundations and
contain inappropriate elements. The tendency to apply convenient contemporary
tags - for example labelling Buddhism `eco-friendly' - may only serve to obscure
what is in reality a different set of attitudes or underlying concerns. As
Harris notes:
... ecological concerns are quintessentially modern
concerns with origins that can be traced to the collapse of traditional Western
cosmological certainties under the impact of science. Indeed, there may be some
justification in the view that the eco-catastophist outlook is the contemporary
inheritor of Judaeo-Christian eschatology with its great emphasis on the events
leading up to the `end of history.' If this geneaology is accepted, the lack of
any explicit discussion of environmental ethics in the foundational documents of
Buddhism is understandable. We simply should not expect to find coherent
discussion of a topic that, strictly speaking, is not crucial to the Buddhist
understanding of reality.
Having sounded this warning, Harris goes on to note the
feature of Buddhism which seem to be in harmony with the concerns of
contemporary ecology. The First Precept is of importance here, as is the thrifty
and frugal lifestyle of the monks, which contrasts with the `untrammeled
consumerism' of modern life. The existence of a monastic rule which obliges
monks to avoid causing injury to plants and animals also seems to point in the
direction of a rudimentary ecological concern. In the light of other factors,
however - such as that monks are not required to be vegetarian - Harris takes
the view that `None of this seems closely tied to an explicitly
ecological
ethic.'
Certain
aspects of Buddhist teaching seem to favour ecological concerns. The notion of
an `extended kinship' among all spheres of existence - animal, human, and divine
- serves to foster solidarity with other forms of life. The Buddhist virtue of
'loving-kindness' (metta) which is to be practised towards all beings, seems to
strengthen further the bonds with other creatures. Harris, however, detects an
ambiguity in these Buddhist beliefs and practices. Meditation, as an inward
practice, is not at all like ecological activism, and loving-kindness has
individuals as its object rather than species. The ideas that species must be
valued in their own right is a cornerstone of modern ecology, but appears to be
absent in Buddhism.
There is
also evidence that early Buddhism is `fundamentally dysteleologic.' The
doctrinal teaching that all life is suffering, and that the world is impermanent
and in decline, hardly seems a good foundation on which to construct an
environmental ethic. In the light of this world-view the obvious question is
`Why bother?' If there is no intrinsic purpose or direction to time or history
it is difficult to attach any ultimate value or meaning to the things of this
world. This recalls a tendency within Buddhism, referred to earlier, which
maintains that the priority is not to improve the world but to escape from it
into nirvana at the earliest possible opportunity.
The
prospects for a more positive set of ecological credentials seem greater in East
Asian than Indian Buddhism. Here is found the notion that all things - even
trees, grass and inanimate objects like the earth - have the capacity to reach
nirvana. This is because all reality is permeated by the `Buddha nature,' and
contains within itself the `seed of enlightenment' (tathagatagarbha). This is
nicely expressed in the Zen haiku of Kaga no
Chiyo
(1701-1775 CE):
All I pick
up
At the ebb tide
Is alive!
It is this
ecologically-friendly face of East-Asian Buddhism that has been received most
favourably in the West amongst ecologists. The tendency has been to contrast the
enlightened `naturalism' of Buddhism with the more aggressive and destructive
attitude towards nature supposedly evinced by the Judaeo-Christian tradition,
which is seen by influential writers such as Lynn White as a major culprit in
the contemporary eco-crisis. Here again, however, Harris sounds a note of
caution against adopting too readily what may be `romanticised and nostalgic'
visions found in art and literature which have more to do with local cultural
and historical circumstances than with the deep structure of Buddhist thought.
He concludes by questioning the intellectual pedigree of what has come to be
termed `ecoBuddhism':
In fact,
much that masquerades under the label of ecoBuddhism, a neologism employed to
denote the contemporary Buddhist response to the challenge of ecological
degradation premised on the prioritisation of `mental states,' on analysis,
turns out to be an uneasy partnership between Spinozism, New Age religiosity and
highly selective Buddhism.
Our
attention is turned in the following three chapters from the world of animals
and nature back to human-centred issues. The next two chapters are concerned
with issues in medical ethics: the first deals with an issue at the beginning of
life, and the second with a moral dilemma at the end of life.
In chapter
six, Robert Florida provides an overview of Buddhist approaches to abortion, one
of the most controversial and divisive of contemporary moral issues. Rather
surprisingly, and in complete contrast to the voluminous literature and abundant
pronouncements and position statements available on this topic in the West,
there has been little debate on the matter in the Buddhist cultures of Asia.
Florida suggests some of the reasons for this curious hiatus and makes a point
which strikes many observers, namely the apparent reluctance of those in
positions of religious authority within Buddhism to take a position on
controversial moral questions. The profile of the Buddhist establishment on
questions of this kind could scarcely be lower (this applies not only to
Thailand), and in many respects their pronouncements and public statements seem
geared to a bygone age rather than the needs of today.
Florida
then turns his attention to traditional Buddhist teachings on ethics,
embryology, and abortion. Drawing mainly on Theravada sources supplemented by
Tibetan teachings, he explains how traditional Buddhist notions of rebirth
generate a distinctive yet quite clear position on this question. Since
conception marks not the beginning of personal existence but a continuation of
it, the moral status of a new conceptus is held to be equal to that of its
recently-deceased predecessor. In other words, there is no moral distinction to
be drawn between the entity in the womb, a young child and a mature adult. The
basic Buddhist position, therefore, is that abortion is included along with
other acts of homicide as a breach of the First Precept against taking life.
At the same
time, Buddhist ethics places a great deal of emphasis on the motivation with
which an act is performed, so the intention of those involved has a large part
to play in assessing moral culpability in individual cases. Furthermore, in the
light of the doctrine of dependent origination (paticcasamuppada), which holds
that all phenomena are causally interrelated, it would be pertinent to look at
the total context and the impact on all those affected rather than to evaluate
the significance of the act in isolation.
The
Buddhist perspective on abortion is further nuanced by the influence of the
different Asian cultures with which Buddhism interacted over the course of the
past two millennia. In order to provide as balanced and representative a picture
as possible, Florida surveys the contemporary situation in three different
countries: Thailand, Japan, and Korea. Thailand receives the most attention, and
it quickly becomes clear that in practice the official or canonical stance on
abortion is more respected in the breach than the observance. Florida provides
useful information on the legal regulation of abortion in Thailand as well as
statistics on the number of abortions performed per annum. Somewhat surprising
for a country in which Buddhism - a religion renowned for its respect for life -
is the state religion, and in which 90 per cent of Thais are Buddhists,
abortions are running at some 50 per cent higher than the number in the USA for
the equivalent number of citizens. `Thailand', he writes, `essentially has
therapeutic abortion on demand.' 85 per cent or more of abortions are obtained
by married women, the majority employed in agricultural work, who appear to use
it as a means of birth control. Florida refers to an estimated 300,000 abortions
per year, the majority of which are illegal. While only an estimate, the figure
represents an increase of two thirds on the annual total for the United Kingdom
(Thailand has a population of 60 million, one or two million higher than the
United Kingdom).
Under Thai
law abortion is permitted for therapeutic reasons where `it is necessary for the
sake of the woman's health,' or if the pregnancy is the result of rape. Under
the current law, the Penal Code of 1956, strict penalties are prescribed for
abortions performed illegally outside of these exceptions: three years in prison
and/or a heavy fine for the woman, and five years imprisonment and/or a heavy
fine for the abortionist. The heavy penalties reflect the traditional Buddhist
disapproval of abortion, but the high abortion statistics show there is another
side to the matter. This is confirmed in opinion polls which, Florida notes,
`reflect the marked dissonance between Thai religious theory, which judges
abortion to be an unskilful violation of Buddhist principles, and Thai practical
reality, which is that abortion is very common.' The Thai attitude to abortion
is paradoxical, since while most Thais regard abortion as immoral, a majority
also believe the legal grounds for obtaining it should be relaxed.
The
situation in Japan, where Buddhism is not the state religion, also shows
interesting variations from the canonical norm. Florida takes as the focus of
his discussion the recent phenomenon of mizuko kuyo, a memorial service
performed following an abortion or miscarriage. He explains the Buddhist context
of the ritual, which emerged in the 1960s, and summarises the different
scholarly opinions and interpretations of this social phenomenon, including
feminist and other readings. Interestingly, the practice has also been adopted
by at least one Zen Buddhist group in the United States.
From Japan,
Florida turns to neighbouring South Korea, sometimes described as an `abortion
paradise.' Although abortion is officially illegal, it is, as in Thailand,
widely practised. More than half of married women in Korea have had at least one
abortion, with one third reporting two or more. In particular, so many female
fetuses have been aborted that it is estimated there will be a shortage of wives
for males of a certain age group. After a long silence, Buddhists have recently
begun to express views on the subject of abortion. Particularly notable are the
pro-life publications of a Buddhist monk, the Venerable Sok Myogak, and the
post-abortion ceremonies held by the nun Venerable Songdok.
Turning
from the beginning of life to its end, Pinit Ratanakul's chapter `To Save or Let
Go: Thai Buddhist Perspectives on Euthanasia' returns us to Thailand to consider
another important contemporary moral problem in a specific cultural setting. New
medical technology has raised issues which traditional Thai ethics - based
largely on early Buddhism - do not seem well equipped to deal with. The author
notes that `The new life-support technologies have blurred the line between
prolongation of life and prolongation of the dying process, and have raised
questions about the adequacy of the traditional definition of death as the
cessation of all vital signs.' Although Buddhism has long been concerned
philosophically with death as a feature of the human condition, it has not
heretofore had a problem about distinguishing the living from the dead. Apart
from the empirical issues presented by the new technology, like the problem of
defining death, a host of thorny ethical ones cluster around the final stages of
life. For example:
Is the
refusal of life-preserving treatment by artificial means a morally acceptable
option or does it constitute a kind of suicide prohibited by Buddhist teachings?
Is it morally wrong for doctors, nurses and families to withdraw life-preserving
treatments or to stop such treatment, once these have begun? Are such actions
the same as `killing' patients or are there important ethical distinctions to be
made between 'letting-go-of-life' by withholding or stopping treatment, and
actual `killing' or causing death?
The case of
the late Thai monk Venerable Buddhadasa Bhikkhu brought these issues to the
attention of the Thai public in recent times. Buddhadasa made a `living will'
stating that he did not wish his life to be prolonged by extraordinary means and
preferred a natural death. However, when he suffered a serious stroke in 1993 at
the age of 86 after earlier minor ones, a debate arose among his disciples as to
whether he should be hospitalised. In the end he was, and the doctors insisted
on continuing with treatment that contravened his wishes as expressed in the
advance directive he had made. Although both sides - devotees and doctors -
sought to do what was best, the incident came to be seen as providing a stark
example of the contrast between the values of modern medicine and those of
traditional Buddhism.
The case of
Buddhadasa also engendered a lively debate among Thai Buddhists on the question
of euthanasia, and Ratanakul locates his discussion of this issue within the
context of the Buddhist doctrine of karma (Pali: kamma). This teaches that the
moral and physical are intertwined, and that physical conditions may have moral
or psychological causes. As such, treating only the physical symptoms of a
disease may not result in a cure. What is important is that the whole person
should be well, both spiritually and physically. But what if a cure is
impossible, as in the final stages of terminal illness? Is `mercy killing' ever
justified in these contexts? Ratanakul suggests an interesting psychological
dynamic may be at work in the case of physicians who perform euthanasia. Despite
the good motivation of wishing to prevent suffering, in Buddhist terms the
physician may well be acting out of aversion (dosa) to the patient's suffering.
As such, it is fundamentally his own repugnance and `hidden hatred' of the
patient's pain and suffering which leads him to perform euthanasia. This line of
reflection leads Ratanakul to the conclusion: `Therefore from the view of
Buddhist psychology "mercy-killing" is not really a benevolent act. It is done
from ill will and thus has bad kammic effects both for the doctor and the
patient.'
So much for
what has become known as `active euthanasia.' But what about `passive
euthanasia'? Ratanakul sees this as a more complex issue, and one about which
the majority of lay Thai Buddhists are uncertain. `Some Thai Buddhists,' he
notes, `recognize that there is a real moral distinction between
"letting-go-of-life" or allowing a patient to die and directly and intentionally
taking life. For them, allowing a patient to die does not violate the precept
and is considered an altruistic action for those involved.' Buddhist ethics
places great emphasis on intention, and in the case of euthanasia much depends
on the motivation of those in whose hands the decision rests. For example, is it
done from a desire to relieve suffering, to speed the inheritance of an estate,
or to harvest organs for transplantation? The moral assessment of each of these
situations may vary, and so a case-by-case approach to the problem seems wisest.
Given the
increasing
number of cases of patients who recover from so-called `irreversible' comas, and
the obvious scope for abuse, lay Thai Buddhists take the view that it would be
unwise to adopt general policies on passive euthanasia. Instead, Buddhism
emphasises the principle of interrelatedness (paticcasamuppada) when assessing
situations of this kind. As noted above, this is a universal principle that
states that everything exists in mutual dependency. As such, it discourages
unilateral decisions and calls for dialogue and discussion with full recognition
of the effects our actions have on others. The most appropriate environment for
the care of terminal patients, and the one most congenial to Buddhist values,
Ratanakul concludes, is the hospice, for the following reasons:
The success
in pain-relief and the atmosphere and policies of the hospice movement indicate
that no one needs die neglected, alone, shunted aside by doctors and nurses,
busy with the living yet unconscious and hooked to machines, kept from their
families. The hospice movement shows that death with dignity and humane
treatment is still possible in our time.
Clearly,
had hospice care been available in the case of the Venerable Buddhadasa, the
tragic course of events surrounding his death could have been avoided, and the
suffering of all concerned reduced.
Developments in medical science present a unique set of problems, but so do
other facets of the modern world. Business, commerce, and economic concerns have
come to dominate modern life. What is the proper role of Buddhism in this new
era where, as one writer puts it, `corporations rule the world'? This is the
question David Bubna-Litic sets out to answer in the final chapter. He begins by
reminding us just how rapid the changes have been in modern times:
In the two
hundred or so years since the Industrial Revolution began, the world has seen a
period of unprecedented change. Our capacity to transform raw materials into
products has grown exponentially. For example, total global economic output has
expanded by more in each of the past four decades than from prehistory to the
middle of this century.
The impact
of these changes on individuals has been significant, and it is surely true that
`the dominance of work in our lives leaves gaps in our humanity.' The giddy pace
of modern life seems to leave less and less time for spiritual pursuits. In
society as a whole, the gap between rich and poor seems every wider, and in the
world economy poor nations resort to sweatshop industries, corruption, violence
and political repression to meet the needs of more affluent countries.
In seeking
a Buddhist response to these concerns, Bubna-Litic draws a parallel between the
Buddha's rejection of a life of comfort and luxury and the increasing
dissatisfaction of many people today with a contemporary ethos which values only
status and material success. The central theme in the legend of the Buddha's
life, however, is not out-and-out rejection but the search for a productive
`middle way.' It was when he adopted the `middle way' after six years of
austerity that the Buddha quickly gained enlightenment. So what is the proper
role of `the bodhisattva in business?' It would seem to call for a relationship
with the everyday world rather than a flat rejection of it. But what form of
organizational structure is most appropriate for this? The monastery, the
corporation, or does some new communal framework need to be developed as a
suitable vehicle for Buddhism in the modern world? To answer this question,
Bubna-Litic turns back to the fundamental doctrines and moral teachings of the
Buddha. The principle of interdependency must surely be acknowledged in any
organisational structure. So too must the vows of refuge and the Precepts.
Modern business techniques that are compatible with Buddhist teachings, like
Julian Gresser's methodology for negotiation, can be incorporated. Using the
Samurai technique of approaching new situations at work with `a stance of open
awareness' can allow us to respond intuitively, without expectations or
prejudice. Work situations also provide the opportunity to cultivate the
spiritual virtue of integrity through `a spiral pathway of learning.' Given the
short-term focus of modern organisations they can be chaotic, and full of
conflict. The practice of Buddhism can help us withstand the pain and
disappointment which arises from the overidentification with projects and plans
we become involved with by stripping away the projections and emotional
over-investment we make in them.
Integrity is also important in dealing with the success and financial and other
rewards which business acumen can bring. Buddhism teaches how wealth should be
distributed and emphasises an attitude of inner detachment so that our inner
integrity is undisturbed and unthreatened either by failure or success.
Bubna-Litic suggests that `it is possible to develop an alternative framework
for navigating work life that resonates well with Buddhist precepts and may shed
new light on "right livelihood".' This framework contains two important and
interrelated elements. The first is the development of detachment, and alongside
this a lifestyle that is simple, healthy, and frugal. The second element is to
live and work with integrity. Work cannot be separated from other areas of life,
and the workplace can become just as much a forum for personal growth and
spiritual development as the monastery. In terms of organisations, also,
integrity is capable, like DNA, of forming many different structures depending
on the local environment. The encounter with the West provides a new challenge
regarding the integration of Buddhist practice and commerce.
The
assumptions of the world of commerce, basically those of egoism and sensual
materialism, are quite different from those which underlie the Dharma, namely
selflessness and detachment. Can they co-exist, or will one overcome the other?
Bubna-Litic is optimistic and concludes:
As more
Buddhist join the commercial world and negotiate their work lives with
integrity, changes will naturally emerge at the collective level. These cannot
be prescribed. What will emerge from this new growth of Buddhism in the West
hopefully will express itself with the grace and beauty of nature in the market
place.
What
general conclusions can be drawn from this book about contemporary Buddhist
ethics? The overall tone of the chapters can be described as one of guarded
optimism. The authors on the whole seem to feel cautiously
optimistic
about the prospects for Buddhism in the modern world, and believe that Buddhism
can make a useful contribution to contemporary moral issues. At the same time,
they also point out the many pitfalls and problems that face those who seek
today to tap the spring of Buddhist moral wisdom for guidance.
In large
part these dangers fall into two groups. The first concerns the hermeneutical
problems of making ancient scriptures speak to new contexts. This is a
challenging but not insuperable task, and it is one that is at present being
undertaken in other religious traditions. There is no reason why Buddhism cannot
meet this challenge in the same way, perhaps in dialogue with other faiths.
The second
danger is more subtle, and concerns what might be termed `cultural
misappropriation.' This occurs when contemporary Western views are `read back'
into an Asian tradition. Many Westerners, for example, find Buddhism attractive
because it seems congenial to their own liberal ideology. Thus, in contrast to
much of what is perceived as negative in Western religion, Buddhism appears to
be open-minded, rational, ecofriendly, kind to animals, pacifist, and neither
authoritarian nor doctrinaire. The `voluntary' or `optional' nature of the
Buddhist precepts, for example, is frequently contrasted with the `Commandments'
of Christianity. The essays in this book, however, show that such a conception -
which for convenience we might term `liberal Buddhism' - is really only a
construct which depends largely for its existence on Western culture, and, in
particular, Christianity. Buddhist sources, as noted above, reveal a much more
untidy and at times contradictory picture made up of different strands. To
select only those which are in harmony with fashionable trends in Western
society is to treat Buddhism superficially, and fail to engage seriously with
its views. It is, however, an understandable and common mistake to project the
assumptions of one's own culture onto another, and to make invisible those parts
of it which do not seem to fit well with our j own preconceptions. Buddhism as a
reality is far from monolithic, and even at the level of individual schools one
encounters nuanced and divergent points of view. This complexity must be
reckoned with in any dialogue with Western ethics.
The purpose
of this book is to open such a dialogue across a broad front. The views
expressed here are far from the last word or the only voices that deserve
attention. The collection as a whole, however, constitutes one of the first
major contributions to a range of contemporary moral issues from a Buddhist
perspective, and may serve as a representative example of the present state of
reflection on the issues surveyed.
insert content here