The
Predicament of Postmodern Theology: Radical Orthodoxy or Nihilist
Textualism? by Gavin Hyman (Westminster John Knox Press) It
may be said that radical orthodoxy and nihilist textualism provide two
radically antithetical theological responses to our postmodern predicament.
What is particularly striking, however, is that these two responses have largely
failed to confront and engage each other. In particular, radical orthodoxy makes
serious and challenging criticisms of postmodern nihilism to which the nihilist
textualist writers have manifestly failed to respond. Indeed, not only nihilist
textualism but also other forms of modern and liberal theology have failed to
take up Milbank's gauntlet. Although many theologians have been quick to
distance themselves from the radical orthodox enterprise, an extended and
thorough critique of the project has yet to appear.
It is the primary aim of this book to disrupt this absence
by providing a rigorous critique of radical orthodoxy from a postmodern
perspective. This perspective has something in common with the nihilist
textualism of Cupitt and especially Taylor. It will become clear, however, that
the process of "out-narration" is not unidirectional, and that radical
orthodoxy itself allows one to perceive many deficiencies in the projects of
nihilist textualism. In particular, it will be seen that nihilist textualism is,
in many respects, insufficiently postmodern. I therefore point toward a third
postmodern disposition, a "fictional nihilism" that is neither the radical
orthodoxy of John Milbank nor the nihilist textualism of Don Cupitt. A
subsidiary, though equally necessary, aim of this book is to provide an analysis
of the relationship of these two versions of postmodern theology to each other,
to the postmodern condition out of which they both, in different ways, emerge,
and to the philosophical epoch of modernity against which they both, in
different ways, react. It is only out of such an analysis that a properly
informed evaluation can emerge.
In chapter 1, I provide an account of the cultural and
philosophical condition of postmodernity, drawing in particular on the work of
Fredric Jameson, Perry Anderson, and Jean-Francois Lyotard. I then discuss and
summarize the two main theological responses to such a condition, taking Don
Cupitt as a paradigm of nihilist textualism and John Milbank as a paradigm of
radical orthodoxy. I show that whereas Cupitt is much more willing to embrace
this cultural condition, together with its implications for theology, Milbank
embraces it only insofar as it allows for the return of theology. Once theology
has returned, Milbank then provides a theological critique of the very
post-modernism that made his theology possible. Milbank's attitude to
post-modernism is therefore much more ambivalent than Cupitt's. I suggest that
the differing evaluations of postmodernism on the parts of Cupitt and Milbank
cannot be understood apart from their respective evaluations of modernity, a
discussion I turn to in chapter 2.
Whereas it is often thought that modernity began somewhere
around the sixteenth century, particularly with the philosophy of Rene
Descartes, I consider the work of Hans Urs von Balthasar and other, more recent
scholars (including those of radical orthodoxy) to show how many aspects of
Cartesian philosophy are inconceivable without certain theological innovations
in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries on the part of such theologians as
John Duns Scotus. If the logic of Scotist thought was manifested in Descartes's
philosophy, then it reached its culmination in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant.
I show how this "modernist" philosophical tradition is given contemporary
expression in the work of liberal theologians such as John Hick. Furthermore, I
show how Cupitt's postmodernism emerged organically and progressively out of a
similar liberal theology that he previously espoused. In this way, it can be
seen that nihilist textualism essentially stands in a relationship of continuity
with modernity, even if it is shown that the logic of modernity must ultimately
subvert itself. In contrast, radical orthodoxy is emphatically discontinuous
with modernity, insisting that the project of modernity is itself a logical
outworking of the fundamentally secular and hence "heretical" moves of Duns
Scotus. Insofar as postmodernism is a (continuous) exacerbation of modernity,
it, too, is fundamentally secular and heretical, and both modernity and
postmodernity must be left behind in favor of theology. But insofar as
postmodernism interrogates and criticizes modernity, this aspect may be embraced
by Milbank as an ally for his cause. Thus, the respective stances of Cupitt and
Milbank toward postmodernism can be understood only in terms of these thinkers'
antithetical evaluations of modernity.
In chapter 3, I consider the question of why Cupitt has
failed to confront the challenge presented to his work by radical orthodoxy. I
argue that he is ultimately unable to address the challenge because his project
is located within a realist/ anti-realist framework that is a manifestation of
the dualism of modernity. This means that any viewpoint or narrative that lies
outside this framework is reduced to nothing or is distorted by being subsumed
into a framework it refuses. I show how Cupitt follows the latter strategy,
insisting that radical orthodox theologians are "non-realists in disguise." The
"otherness" of radical orthodoxy as an-"other" theology is thereby destroyed,
and the essence of its viewpoint is severely distorted, for Cupitt insists on
interpreting radical orthodoxy in terms of a frame-work that radical orthodoxy
itself refuses. The result is that Cupitt is unable to identify and confront the
true essence of its challenge. I argue, therefore, that if a critique of radical
orthodoxy is to be effective, it must move beyond and leave behind the
realist/anti-realist framework altogether.
I undertake such a critique in chapter 4, where I again
take John Milbank's work as a paradigm of radical orthodox theology. My
criticisms here are of two main types. First, I argue that Milbank's absolute
conception of the theological metanarrative is itself undesirable in its
inevitable effects. I show how it gives rise to a dualistic opposition between
theology and nihilism, and that this, in turn, gives rise to a whole series of
derivative dualisms. I show how the initial dualism gives rise to a violent
warfare between theology and nihilism as well as to violent readings and
treatments of of all other, subsidiary narratives. I also suggest that Milbank's
metanarrative resists the "mastery" of modernist metanarratives only with
difficulty. These characteristics are particularly problematic because much of
Milbank's rhetoric depends on his contention that (his) theology is the only
metanarrative that can resist dualism, violence, and mastery.
Second, I argue that Milbank's absolute metanarrative is,
in any case, inherently unstable, and that it repeatedly deconstructs itself
from within. I suggest that Milbank can resist mastery only by invoking a
fictionalist (or nihilist?) supplement that cannot be derived solely from the
theological metanarrative itself. The very existence of such a supplement
undermines the status of Milbank's metanarrative as an absolute metanarrative. I
demonstrate that in Milbank's project, the Christian (meta)narrative is itself
"positioned" by Milbank's own (meta)narrative, which is again distinct from the
Christian narrative. Furthermore, when Milbank provides an account of the way
in which his (meta)narrative "out-narrates" other (meta)narratives, he thereby
invokes a "meta-metanarrative" that converges remarkably with the metanarrative
of nihilism he is so concerned to reject. In this way, Milbank's absolute
metanarrative appears to deconstruct itself from within, for when every
metanarrative is positioned by a higher level of metanarrative, the very concept
of metanarrative is itself destabilized. It seems that, in post-modernism, a
metanarrative is as impossible as it is unavoidable.
Having criticized radical orthodoxy from a postmodern
perspective, I reverse the direction of confrontation in chapter 5. Here, I
defend postmodern nihilism from Milbank's virulent attacks and
(mis)interpretations. I distinguish between a metaphysical nihilism and a
fictional nihilism and argue that Milbank's "out-narration" of nihilism is
directed solely at a metaphysical form of nihilism. This form of nihilism
espouses a metaphysics of the nothing, the nothing that is. As such, it is, as
Milbank claims, a disguised form of positivism and consequently refuses all
nihilistic implications. I claim that nihilism is properly accomplished only
with a weakening of its own ontological status: when it is recognized that
nihilism is no more than a fiction. The fictionalism that nihilism ascribes to
everything else must ultimately be ascribed even to itself. Furthermore, I argue
that Nietzsche himself would be better interpreted as a fictional nihilist, and
that any attempt to read him in a metaphysical fashion does undue violence to
texts. I argue that it is precisely such a fictional nihilism that Milbank fails
to con front. Insofar as postmodern nihilists are themselves fictional
nihilists, the meta physical nihilism that Milbank out-narrates is, in effect, a
straw man. In the face of a properly accomplished fictional nihilism, Milbank's
criticisms would appeal to subside.
Finally, in chapter 6, I consider what a writing of
fictional nihilism might loo like. First, I argue that Cupitt's nihilism is
insufficiently fictional. The difficulyhere is that Cupitt espouses what is
essentially a modern postmodernism, in which the "other" is repressed. When the
"other" is eradicated, everything is present and nothing is hidden. This is the
modern utopia of the presence of the present. Without an "other," a "principle
of travel," Cupitt's narrative becomes static, stable, and insufficiently
reflexive. Cupitt wants to "overcome" reflexivity
rather than embrace it. The result of this is that he
appears to lapse into what he himself describes as an "obsolete metaphysics."
Mark C. Taylor rectifies Cupitt's neglect in this regard. Constantly aware of
the "other" that always returns,
It is my suggestion, however, that such a movement is
insufficiently embodied. Refusing and passing over every location,
exodus of discourse," he nevertheless moves through the
finite, through narratives, particularities, bodies, and locations. Although all
discourses must ultimately be left behind in the name of the "other," they can
be properly left behind only if they have first been inhabited. I also resist
the attempts of some theologians to "domesticate" de Certeau's writings in
favor of a more orthodox theological reading. For although theology, as a
heterological discourse par excellence, is a narrative that de Certeau wants to
wander through, his heterological concern for the "other" means that theology
itself must also, ultimately, be left behind.
I suggest, therefore, that Michel de Certeau shows us not
so much the way forward as the way to "get lost" in our postmodern condition. He
narrates an endless exodus of discourse that may serve as a paradigm for a
writing of fictional nihilism. His writings exemplify the a/logic of the
neither/nor that rejects the either/or of both radical orthodoxy and nihilist
textualism. In the conclusion, I point toward a third territory for postmodern
theology, in which theology repeatedly "returns" to haunt the movement of
perpetual departure. In this sense, we can never be done with theology. But this
return cannot be absolute, and the movement of perpetual departure can no longer
be anchored in a theological origin. To be anchored in this way is to return to
theology as metanarrative, a return that is as undesirable as it is impossible.
Understood in this sense, theology must always also "depart."
Having now completed the prelude or introduction to these
particular wanderings, we must now attempt the impossible: that is, we must now
attempt to begin at the beginning.
insert content here
insert content here